Intrinsic Desire and Morality: Entomological Revelations
Darwinism is all the rage among contemporary ethicists, and
with good reason. Since no informed thinker can deny the centrality of natural
selection to our development as the human beings we are, our values, like any
of our other traits, must conform to the constraint of survival. In other
words, however much we are by nature wedded to notions like justice and beauty
and reason and curiosity and charity, the root cause must have to do with their
furtherance of, or at least compatibility with, our survival under the
conditions of our evolution on this planet. Yet on the face of it, our values
often appear indifferent to and even in conflict with our survival. How could
this be? What, after all, has rapture by a sunset, or the fervor to understand
what happened before the Big Bang, or abhorrence at cruelty to other animals,
etc. ad inf., to do with our individual or even collective advantage in the
struggle for existence?
Much
ingenious thought has gone into addressing this question, particularly as
regards altruism. For example, imagine A, who has some “altruism genes,”
competing in the game of survival with E, who is a thoroughgoing egoist with
only “egoism genes.” E would appear to have the advantage, since he will do
whatever it takes to survive, whereas A would, on some occasions, sacrifice
herself for others; so that we might expect E to survive and A to perish, and
hence the trait of altruism itself to disappear from the population. But
consider that if A’s altruism were directed toward her offspring, then A’s very
self-sacrifice could assure the survival of her genetic trait of altruism in
the next generation, and so on in the same manner into the indefinitely far
future; whereas E’s uninhibited selfishness might inhibit the survival of his
offspring, thereby bringing about the demise of that trait in short order.
Thus, what at first might appear to be a paradox turns out to follow from the
simple logic of natural selection.[1]
Noticing a spider by my kitchen
sink the other day led me to consider the question of “paradoxical traits” more
broadly. The tiny creature huddled in the dark, presumably patiently awaiting
his or her prey. The thought struck me: “This spider is not thinking, ‘I had best huddle in the dark, the better to obtain
food’.” Then followed a long train of other thoughts (in me, not the spider).
First was that many people would infer from this initial observation that the
spider – and by extension all other nonhuman animals – is a mere mechanism;
that is, that instead of reasoning to a conclusion about how to behave, the
spider merely acts by instinct.
But I came
to a different conclusion about the spider’s mental life, indeed, the opposite
conclusion. To me it seemed obvious that the spider, while certainly not
reasoning to a conclusion, nevertheless was acting on the basis of a rich
mental life, and in fact one similar to ours. For I suddenly appreciated that
the spider was probably responding to the darkness with what, in the human
case, we would call a preference or a desire. That spider likes the darkness.
What that spider feels is the welcoming pleasure of basking in shade, perhaps
in much the way you and I would take pleasure in finding shelter on a
sweltering sunny day in the tropics. There is nothing fundamentally alien about
the spider’s experience. There is no impassable gap between us, no deep mystery
about “what it is like” to be a different sort of creature from ourselves.[2]
Nor, therefore, is there any need to “anthropomorphize” in order to empathize
with him or her (if it is sexed); we need only zoomorphize, so to speak, since
surely all animals – now using “animals” to include humans – share one or
another of many mental traits and not only physical traits.
Thus,
neither do we “reason to a
conclusion” when seeking shade in the normal run of cases. Yes, we might do so
in special circumstances, or when needing to be reminded of the obvious because
we have been distracted, etc. But for the most part, if we find the sun too
hot, or if we wish to hide from a pursuer, or from the pursued, and so on, we
will seek the darkness as a matter of course. Say “instinctively,” if you like,
thereby bringing us “down” to the “level” of other animals; or say instead, and
as I prefer to do, that all animals, human or otherwise, usually act on the
basis of desire.
But there
is much more to say about this, even in my “desire” terms. Of particular note
is that the desires that characterize us as animals are intrinsic ones (what I called “desire1” in the previous
section). An intrinsic desire is a desire to do something “for its own sake.”
This is to be distinguished, in the first instance, from an extrinsic or
instrumental desire (desire2), which is a desire to do something for
some further reason or “ulterior motive.” So, as illustrated in the previous
section, if you wanted to go for a walk in order to lose weight, and only for
that reason, since otherwise you are averse to any kind of exercise (which is
how you became overweight), then your desire to go for a walk would be merely
instrumental. But if you desired to go for a walk simply for the pleasure of
stretching your legs and seeing the sights on a beautiful day, then your desire
to go for a walk would be intrinsic. (Of course a desire could also be both.)
So that
little spider, as I see him, has an intrinsic desire to huddle in darkness …
just as you and I have an intrinsic desire to huddle by a fire on a cold day.
Now there are several things to note about this. First is that these desires
could be construed as serving instrumental purposes. Thus, the spider is
huddling in order not to starve, and you and I are huddling in order not to
freeze. As suggested at the outset, the common denominator here is survival. So
intrinsic desire would seem to have a function that makes sense in evolutionary
terms.[3]
Nevertheless, my main point is that these desires are intrinsic for all that,
at least in the normal run of cases, since it is usually not necessary to, and
could be positively maladaptive to have to, make an explicit inference from end
to means in order to have these desires in the relevant circumstances. Our
experience, therefore, is not, “I am
cold; therefore I should huddle by
this fire,” but is rather, “Oh, there’s a fire. Umm, warmth feels good.” So in
this respect, to this degree, we are no different from the spider, who does not
reason that s/he needs to huddle in the darkness, but only feels drawn to the
darkness and satisfied to be in it.
What has
this to do with (so-called) paradoxical traits? It seems to me that many if not
all of our intrinsic desires veer away from our evolutionary concerns, and in
so doing carve out the special domain of the ethical. I have already suggested
that there is no genuine paradox here, since explanatory hypotheses are
available to bridge the gap between evolution’s demands and the sometimes
seemingly opposed desires we have. Nature moves us by indirection; nature
speaks to us through feelings. Feelings are our common denominator as animals,
which we tendentiously call “instincts” in other animals and “reasons” in
ourselves. But in fact both the spider and we are moved by the desire to get
out of the heat or light and into the shade by nature’s mechanism for
protecting us from predators or our skin from radiation or for feeding us, etc.[4]
What I want now to emphasize beyond
this is the centrality of intrinsic
desire to ethics. This is a matter of interest and importance, I shall argue,
because ethics is usually conceived to be about a different phenomenon that is
easily confused with intrinsic desire. This other phenomenon is inherent value. Inherent value is most
directly confused with what we could call intrinsic
value, after the intrinsic desire
that gives rise to it. Thus, if you desired to go for a walk for its own sake,
then your desire would be intrinsic
and so therefore would be the value
you attributed to what you desired – walking would have intrinsic value for
you. Now suppose you were a real walking enthusiast, who wanted to spread the
gospel of walking to all and sundry. Then a subtle shift might occur in your
conception of walking’s value, from something you valued subjectively to
something that possessed objective
value. That latter is what I am calling inherent value.
My main
contention is that this mental move from subjective to objective is a mistake,
and one with enormous, and largely baneful consequences. I don’t mean just
about walking, of course, but in ethics generally.[5]
I take ethics to be reflection on how to live[6]
(with more particular foci on actions, motives, traits, lifestyles, character, and
so forth). But ethics, as I noted in the Introduction, is often more narrowly
defined as the study of morality. And
there’s the rub. For morality, at least on a common understanding, is a domain
of inherent values. It is in morality that we hear about things that we “must”
or “should” or “ought to” do (etc.) tout
court or unconditionally or categorically, which is to say, not because we happen to desire to do
them, since desire is a merely psychological or subjective phenomenon, but
because they have objective value, or, in a teleological ethics, because they
bring about something that has objective value. The term “inherent” is
applicable in that it conveys the idea that the value sticks to the activity (or object or state of affairs) in question,
whether it be walking or truth telling or whatever. We also say that inherent
value is “absolute,” whereas intrinsic value is only “relative” (to one’s
desires); so an action with inherent value is required of us, regardless of our
desiring to do it or not to do it. An action with inherent value is our duty or obligation to perform; similarly, an action with negative inherent
value is prohibited to us, even if we have a strong desire to carry it out (Thou shalt not commit adultery).
Inherent value, according to its proponents, can “stick
to” many different types of things. Correspondingly, there are also many
species of inherent value. Thus, not only can actions like walking or truth
telling be objectively required or right to do[7] (and actions like lying and killing objectively forbidden
or wrong), but also various character traits can be objectively good (or bad),
which we call virtues (or vices), and various states of affairs can be
objectively good (or bad), such as that peace prevails, and persons can be
objectively good (or evil), and various scenes or human artifacts can be
objectively beautiful (or ugly), and various verbal or behavioral routines can
be objectively funny (or unamusing or offensive), and various physical
conditions and exudations etc. can be objectively disgusting (or attractive),
and so on. By contrast, an intrinsic value is an illusion insofar as it seems to inhere in an object, for it is really only a
“projection” of subjective value into the object … analogous to the way we
“project” a color sensation that arises in our brain into some object, like a
red apple.[8]
A red apple is objectively red in the
sense that it reflects light from its surface in such a way that, under
specific conditions, various nerves in our retinas and optic nerves and
cerebral cortices fire in such a way that we experience the sensation of red.
But that sensation is in our brain, not on the apple’s skin, and hence is only
subjective.[9] Someone
else might experience the redness of the apple differently. Indeed, I have
noticed that I myself experience its redness differently under different
lighting conditions, and even with my two eyes severally. Just so, on the
inherentist’s account, someone may, say, intrinsically disvalue Beethoven’s
music, and this disvaluing would be a real phenomenon in his or her brain
induced by sound waves from a performance or a recording that excite various
nerves; but to project that disvaluing into the music itself and thereby
attribute inherent negative value to
it would be a mistake, since Beethoven’s music is objectively of the highest
quality. It has objective value because the value is in the object of our
regard (in this case, Beethoven’s music), not merely in our subjective
experience of that object (our enjoyment or displeasure at listening to
Beethoven’s music).
I accept the above as an analysis
of the contrasting concepts of intrinsic and inherent value. However, I believe
that only intrinsic value exists in reality.[10]
This is certainly a ground-shaking[11]
thought,[12]
and I cannot claim to be fully reconciled to it. Yet it does very definitely
seem now to me to be true. As much as I myself love Beethoven’s music and, when
in its grip, am filled with the sense that the music itself contains objective
worth to the highest degree, I must, in a cooler moment, utterly reject that
valuation. This has definite practical consequences. For while I would still
take pains to attend a nearby concert of Beethoven’s music, since I love to
listen to a good performance of it, I would no longer lift my nose in contempt
for the person who vastly prefers listening to Mantovani. De gustibus non est disputandum.
Of course that motto is a harder
sell when it comes to morality.[13]
It is one thing to suppress one’s disdain for lowbrows, quite another to
suppress one’s outrage at atrocities. Or so it seems. Alas, I have become more
sensitive to the similarities than the differences. When I experience rage at
the person who cuts me off on the highway, or despisal at the Volkswagen
company for deliberately deceiving the public and the government about the
emissions from its diesel vehicles, or contempt for people who continue to eat
animals despite their growing awareness of complicity in needless cruelty and
slaughter, I am now keenly aware of the anger that fuels these feelings[14]
– anger that has its own source of being apart from what is eliciting it (maybe
my general frustration with life’s recalcitrance to my deepest desires), and
that will often make the situation even worse. I therefore consciously strive
to dissolve the feelings by directing my thoughts toward countervailing ideas
and desires; specifically, I remind myself that right and wrong are myths, that
the people with whom I am angry could not have done otherwise than they did,
and that “everyone you meet is fighting a hard battle” (Ian Maclaren if not Philo).[15]
By the same token, I feel less need
to suppress the tendency to objectify colors, and the beauty of Beethoven’s
music, and other nonmoral phenomena, since the effects of these projections are less baneful and may even be net beneficial.
What this still leaves me with are
intrinsic wishes and desires: that drivers use caution, that companies behave
honestly, that human animals refrain from eating all animals.[16]
I deeply care about and desire all of these things, which motivates me to
various actions. But sans the phony patina of morality that layers objective
disvalue atop reckless driving and drivers, dishonest companies, and carnivorous
habits and persons, my actions can be focused on effectiveness, rationality,
universal charity and goodwill, and other ends and values that I intrinsically
like, rather than on venting, retaliating, preaching, punishing, and so forth,
which I dislike both intrinsically and instrumentally (that is, because they
are things I dislike in themselves and also lead to other things I dislike in
themselves or are simply less effective in bringing about what I do like).[17]
This, then, is why I deem intrinsic desire and intrinsic value to be the very
soul of ethics (and of valuing things generally), and reject the standard
interpretation of ethics (and axiology) that places value “in” things (including actions, motives, character traits, sentient
beings, artifacts, etc.). Value is therefore (and in this sense) subjective,
not objective.[18]
And this has various interesting and important ramifications.[19]
As I noted at the outset, one is that we are much more firmly situated in the
animal realm than we are used to suppose, for all animal species, including our
own, appear to be guided by intrinsic desire above all.
Part 2.
But are not human beings superior
in that we can override desires by force of reason? So sometimes we act for the
same kind of reasons, or really feelings, as the spider does, but are we not
also capable of a kind of action, based on reasoning,
that is absolutely unavailable to the spider? Many have drawn this implication
from the behavior of another insect, the sphex wasp. Scientists performed a
simple and clever experiment to debunk this creature’s cognitive aspirations.[20]
The wasp’s typical way of feeding her young is to bring back a cricket for them
to eat in the burrow where they are incubating. Just prior to dragging the
carcass into the burrow, however, the wasp enters to make an inspection,
apparently with intelligent intent to make sure everything is OK. What the
scientists did was pull the cricket a few inches away from the burrow entrance
while the wasp was inside. When the wasp emerged, what did mama do? She dragged
the carcass back to the entrance and then
did another inspection. The scientists pulled the cricket away again. The
wasp emerged again, dragged the carcass back again, and did another inspection.
This was repeated 40 times before the scientists felt they had made their
point: The sphex wasp is not an intelligent being but only a programmed robot,
not a conscious being but only a mechanism.
But I find both that conclusion and
its supposed implication to be highly questionable. The conclusion is
questionable because it makes the same leap of interpretation I criticized in
the case of my spider: There is no need to deny consciousness to a being just
because it does not employ reasoning to decide how to behave. My spider
probably acts on the basis of feeling, just as we usually do; and so too, I
would imagine, the sphex wasp. The scientists merely debunked their own
unwarranted attribution of reasoning to the wasp; there was no reason or need
in the first place to assume that the wasp must figure out whether to inspect the burrow before bringing food to her
young, any more than there is reason or need for a human parent to infer that she or he should check on the
baby every few minutes. In the normal run of cases one simply feels the urge to do so and acts
accordingly.
But, saith the scientists, that is
“the normal run of cases”; the point at issue is whether human beings have the
unique capacity to override feeling by means of reasoning. To this I reply that
the scientists have quite unwarrantedly assumed that reasoning really does make
a difference with human beings. I have two reasons for doubting this, if not
absolutely, at least in the main. One is that human behavior is often (and I
believe typically) just as absurdly repetitive as the wasp’s in the experiment.[21]
The other is that this can take place in the presence of abundant reasoning.[22]
I need only cite an example from my
own life to make these points, since I am sure that my reader can readily identify
with the phenomenon or recognize it in others. I have had an intermittent
relationship with the same woman for the last ten years.[23]
We have often considered getting married. But the “intermittence” is due to
frequent fallings-out over seemingly minor matters. From my point of view the
problem has arisen, first, from her odd failure to observe certain verbal
customs, such as saying (or writing in an email) “Thank you” when I have done
something nice for her. But of course this only rises to the status of a
“problem” when I react in a certain way. And react I often do, since, for
reasons or causes ultimately unknown to me or anyone, I become very irritated
after a string of such occasions and finally express that irritation.
Naturally this has a negative
effect on her in turn, who apparently sees no justification for my irritation.
Perhaps she saw no need to say “Thank you” in the first place. Although of
course she and I have discussed these things many times, I am still unable to
speak definitively on her behalf; so I will speculate about her thoughts and
feelings. She may not feel appreciation for me because she has expectations of
my doing certain things for her as a matter of course; indeed, there would only
be cause for criticism if I failed to do them, but there is no place
for praise or gratitude if I do them.[24]
Or she may in fact feel appreciation for the things I do for her – after all,
why else stay with me all these years, despite our problems? But therefore she
sees no reason to have to verbally
express that appreciation on every occasion. Am I so dense as not to
recognize it? Thus, in either case, my expressions of irritation, not to
mention the irritation itself, are, from her point of view, entirely
gratuitous. So to her they appear mean-spirited, even cruel. And she, being, in
her words, a “very sensitive” person, is deeply hurt by them.
To me this is of course “absurd.” I
too am a very sensitive person … obviously! That’s why supposedly little things
like her not saying “Thank you” are so distressing to me. Can she not at the very least acknowledge that we are alike in
this regard: that our respective hurts are due to our equally sensitive
natures, albeit with respect to different things? Maybe she can, or maybe she
can’t. But the bottom line is that neither of us, despite our insights into
ourself and the other, has proved capable of altering our response one iota in
all these years. She simply cannot assure reliable verbal expression of her
appreciation for the things I do for her, and I simply cannot reliably refrain from expressing my irritation at
her failures to verbally express appreciation. Meanwhile, she simply cannot
cease to feel distressed by my verbal expressions of irritation, no more than I
can cease to feel irritated by her failures to verbally express her
appreciation.
And the result has certainly been
disastrous,[25]
since we both deeply desire marriage, but it is clear that will never happen.
Obviously, however – to complete my argument – we are both doing a lot of
reasoning about the situation. This does not help. Indeed, I can say about
myself, and I don’t doubt it is similarly true for her, that on occasion it is
the reasoning itself that leads to the offending behavior: I reason to the
conclusion that I must speak to her harshly about her inconsiderateness![26]
But just as often it is the opposite: I see abundant reason for not expressing, perhaps even not
feeling, irritation – because it is not warranted by the facts and/or it will
only have negative effects. But to no avail: The irritation arises, and I
express it.[27]
Therefore when I consider the sphex
wasp, I think: C’est moi. And I can
only (scornfully) laugh at the scientists who conclude, on the basis of their
experiment, that the wasp is therefore
different from us, when in fact they have at least as much reason to conclude
that we are the same as that wasp. If only the scientists were as reflective
about the human condition as they have been clever in testing the wasp, they
would not, after the 40th trial, have dismissed the wasp as
inferior, but instead have felt a shock of recognition: “It’s just like us!”[28]
But of course the scientists are human oh so human, and behold the mote in their fellow animal's eye without
considering the beam in their own eye.
Thus my case
for our commonality with other animals due to the preponderant reliance of
behavior on intrinsic desire rather than reasoning. I have presented this as
part of my case for the mythicality of inherent
value, and, all the more, its phony and even baneful role in ethics (and
axiology more generally). An ethics of desire is not only more naturalistically plausible
than an ethics of inherent (absolute, objective, categorical)
value but can also explain why we value intrinsically things
that are not on their face concerned with survival. In ethics it has been specifically morality that is premised on inherent
value. This has been manifest in two main and opposing ways. One is the
utilitarian or consequentialist morality, according to which we are all absolutely
obligated to maximize (or at least to try to maximize) the amount of inherent
good in the world. The other is the deontic or nonconsequentialist morality,
according to which we are all absolutely obligated to do whatever is inherently
right. Neither has any reality apart from its basis in desire, but both cause
great mischief for making us think they do. Hence my recommendation to ditch
morality altogether.
Joel Marks is Professor Emeritus of Philosophy at the University of New Haven and a Bioethics Center Scholar at Yale University. This essay is excerpted from his book Hard Atheism and the Ethics of Desire (Palgrave Macmillan 2016, pp. 97-109).
[1]
The mechanism or mechanisms that assure the persistence of altruism in the
human population are complex and even controversial; indeed, the very nature of
altruism is contested. For a state-of-the-art treatment of the issues, see
Wilson (2015). My example is only for illustrative purposes, to show the
theoretical possibility of accounting for altruism in the seemingly selfish
world of natural selection.
[2] As
Thomas Nagel (1974) famously held there was.
[3] I
am using “evolution” here as synonymous with natural selection, but natural
selection is only one actual, not to mention possible, mechanism of evolution in the broad sense of
undergoing change. The equivocation seems warranted by natural selection’s
prevalence in our current understanding of the evolution of animals. But see and for a (contested) corrective.
[4] It
then becomes possible for “intelligent” creatures like ourselves to exploit
these feelings for contra-survival purposes. Witness blocking reproduction with contraceptives while
having sex solely for pleasure, courting heart disease by gorging on salty
snacks, and growing obese from eating too many highly sweetened desserts
(although any or all of these could also promote our species’ survival prospects in an overpopulated world).
[5]
And most generally, in axiology, the domain or study of value as such. Thus,
axiology encompasses not only ethics but also, for example, aesthetics, which
is another value domain where subjectivity is commonly mistaken for objectivity
(“I love Beethoven’s 5th Symphony” becomes “Beethoven’s 5th
Symphony is magnificent”).
[6]
And also the fruit of that reflection.
[7] The
value of walking “for its own sake” is perhaps more naturally styled as “good”
rather than “right” since we experience it more as an enjoyment than as a duty.
Walking could, however, be styled as a duty or as objectively required in the
instrumental sense, when its value is derived from some further good, such as
health.
[8]
The situation could also be characterized as an interaction between an organism of a certain type, in a certain
state or under certain conditions, and an object (or surface) of a certain
type, in a certain state or under certain conditions. But I still think it
would make sense to characterize the value as a projection, which results from the interaction.
[9]
“Subjective” in the sense of belonging to the subject of the experience, that is, the one who is experiencing the
red color sensation – the experiencer. It is of course an objective fact of the
world that the sensation exists (although its nature is problematic).
[10]
Note that I am not (necessarily)
rejecting all inherent qualities, but
only all inherent values. The former
is a metaphysical notion, not an axiological one. Thus, for example, human
beings may be inherently belligerent (under certain circumstances); I only
reject that belligerence is inherently bad
or good, or right or wrong. Of course
many of us intrinsically dislike belligerence, but that is a
different matter (this being my main point) – and it would still be a different
matter even if we universally, i.e.,
all human beings, disliked it (you could then even say: even if human beings
were inherently averse to belligerence). For that would still be a fact about our
nature and not a fact about the nature of belligerence.
[11]
And grounds-shaking, to coin a term, in that it removes certain considerations
as legitimate grounds for drawing rational conclusions about how to live.
[12]
It is comparable to losing one’s belief in God. Indeed, objectivity is the
secular version of God, since for most nonbelievers (in God) it is the
metaphysical source of value in the world.
[13]
In fact it is potentially a hard sell in any value realm. Consider: “How can
you eat gefilte fish? It’s disgusting!” For someone who feels that way, it is
almost impossible to conceive that the disgustingness of gefilte fish is
entirely relative to the individual. Indeed, this phenomenon can arise outside
the realm of values and in the realm of facts. Consider: “How can you go around
wearing shorts? It’s cold!” The person who says this simply cannot fathom how
her experience of feeling cold could be only a subjective fact about herself
rather than an objective fact about the temperature. Of course we could define “cold” to mean, say, 50 degrees
Fahrenheit or lower; but this would only shift the speaker’s pseudo-objectivity
to the question of whether one is rationally or prudentially permitted to dress
lightly when it’s cold.
[14]
The objectifying impulse is so strong that one can experience not only
disapproval of someone else’s action, etc., but even incredulity. “I simply
cannot believe that they would cut somebody’s head off.” “I simply cannot
believe that they would skin an animal alive.” This is the power of desire. It
is the same force at work when a highly aroused male simply cannot believe that
the person he desires is not also turned on. The result may be rape.
Objectification is dangerous. It is like a weapon, which can be employed for
benign purposes but has a great potential for havoc and must always be handled
with care; and in most situations it may be best for citizens simply to be
unarmed.
[15]
Compare this comment by the Dalai Lama:
Every
night in my Buddhist practice I give and take. I take in Chinese suspicion. I
give back trust and compassion. I take their negative feeling and give them
positive feeling. I do that every day. This practice helps tremendously in
keeping the emotional level stable and steady. (Reported by Newsweek’s
Melinda Liu and Sudip Mazumdar, March 20, 2008)
[16] I
also desire these things instrumentally, since I also like the consequences I
believe they have; for example, cautious driving results in fewer accidents,
injuries, fatalities, etc.
[17]
The second part of Marks (2013e) contains many extended examples of what I find
advantageous about the amoral life.
See also the final section of the present book.
[18]
More precisely: Value is inherently subjective, but it does contain objective
(or harmlessly objectified) components as well, specifically the unevaluative
qualities of the things we value (the honesty we find so virtuous, the
arrangement of lines we find so beautiful, etc.) and the psychological
attitudes that give rise to our valuations (the desire that everyone be honest,
the pleasure at viewing a drawing, etc.).
[19]
Of course I mean “interesting and important” to me, this being in keeping with my subjectivism. However, I sense
(or at least hope) they would be found interesting and important by many others
as well, which is why I bother to write about them.
[20]
Although I will be disagreeing with an interpretation of the wasp’s behavior,
the claim about how exactly the wasp does behave can also be questioned.
Furthermore, my account of the experiment and its conclusions comes from
secondary sources and my own speculations. A folklore has developed around it
(actually a number of experiments were conducted over a century), and it is
that rather than any actual experiment (or experimenters) which is the target
of my critique. See Keijzer (2013) for more details of the history of the experiment and
how it has been appropriated.
[21]
By the way, there is also the possibility that the wasp has good reason to
reinspect the burrow on every occasion. Cf. Merow (2013).
[22]
Following on the preceding note: Merow (2013) applies this latter point to the
wasp (albeit tongue in cheek), attributing reasoning to the wasp in the experiment.
[23]
Indeed it is so intermittent that I call ours an off-again / off-again
relationship.
[24]
Cf. “A Moralist Crosses the Street” in Chapter 4.
[25]
Also comical from a third-party point of view.
[26]
The objectivist about reason and morals might object that I could not possibly
have been reasoning when I decided on
such a course of action, since I was obviously in the throes of passion
(anger). But this is just the kind of Monday morning quarterbacking I object to
in turn. If bad reasoning turns out not to be reasoning at all, then it becomes
trivially true that rationality, i.e., good reasoning, will always lead to the
right conclusion.
[27]
This obviously bodes ill for the desirist project, which is based on reasoning.
But … hope springs eternal!
[28]
Christopher von Bülow (2003) appears to have come to the same conclusion.