Two Opposing Ways that Intuitional Data Bear on Ethical Theory

It is often said that intuitions serve as the data of philosophy. Of course, as with any concept, the notion of intuition is vexed. (And I think the “simple” solution to all the vexation is that our concepts are polysemous. But that’s another story.) But bracketing that problem, perhaps you will find it acceptable for the present purpose to agree that if, say, an ethical theory implied that everyone has an obligation to cut off her pinky finger for no further reason, we will trust our intuition that this makes no sense, and hence that the theory is false or at least needs more work. 

            The point I want to make now is that sometimes it is the intuition that must yield. Obvious examples abound here too. A classic example is that the intuition that the Sun travels around the Earth had to yield to the heliocentric theory. (Note: Often there is a consolation prize. Thus, it remains perfectly kosher to say that the Sun moves across the sky.)  However, because in ethics the relevant intuitions are often tied to deeply felt commitments or desires, they won’t always easily give up the fight. Indeed, I am now convinced that often they never will, so we are left with a relativity of values, and hence also of whatever ethical theories seem “confirmed” by them (although in meta-theory, maybe all could be, given the right additional assumptions or intuitions). 

          A particular example that keeps exercising me is the moral intuition – that is, the strong and abiding sense that some things are (“absolutely”) wrong and other things are not and may even be obligatory. The ethical theory I now favor implies, or at least suggests, that this intuition is flat-out false. But it won’t quit … not even in my breast. But, as I have often pointed out, I have come to view it the way I view an illusion: I will always see the two long lines in the Müller-Lyer as of unequal length, but also know that they are of equal length. Just so, I will always feel that eating animals is wrong, but I now believe I simply don’t like people doing it (a lot!). (Note: Motivationally I see little if any loss here; see for example “Dispelling the Illusion of Motivational Inadequacy in Ethics.” And ethically I see a definite gain; that is, without the bugaboo of morality to rile us, I think the kind of world most of us would like to live in would become more likely.)

            But another “data”/theory problem is perhaps even more intractable. It happens again and again in my experience that someone will hear out my amoralist thesis and arguments and agree with them. But then I observe that they behave quite contradictorily to that professed agreement; that is, they remain moralistic in their actual feelings, attitudes, and behavior. This goes beyond what I mentioned in the previous paragraph, for there I noted that something can be an illusion but recognized as such, and hence ameliorative action taken. What I am talking about now is being taken in by the illusion, such that it is a delusion, despite the professed acceptance of the theory that labels it an illusion.

            For example, having just engaged in a delightful and agreeable conversation about amoralism, a friend and I suddenly found ourselves in disagreement about some particular practical matter; and before you know it, we were arguing (in the nonrational, emotional sense) about which of us was right or good or wrong or bad! Fortunately I was able to put a halt to this downward spiral by recalling myself to my amoralist senses and recognizing that my own fiery feelings were “just feelings” (and hence quite “unjust” in the moral sense); so I withdrew from my own feelings and stopped casting back recriminations at my friend. However, my friend, no doubt for having had but a cursory introduction to the theory he had just acquiesced to, as opposed to my ten+-year immersion in it, remained firmly entrenched in his judgmentalism. Therefore, applying the central precept of my theory, I simply did (said) what I felt stood the best chance of ameliorating the discord in order to achieve the concord I desired more than proving myself “right” or “good.” In a word, I apologized for doing what he didn’t like. And it worked like a charm. (Note: The apology was sincere, but in my amoralist sense of “apology.”)

            Thus Q.E.D.: Sometimes the “data” we rely on for judging the adequacy of a theory would itself (themselves) profitably yield to the theory. For the data in my interaction/altercation with my friend were moralist feelings; but, at least in my own case, the power of the theory of amoralism overcame them, and the result was vastly preferred by both of us to what the alternative would have been, viz., each of us being angry at the other in our perceived self-righteousness.

Popular posts from this blog

Closing the Gaps

Who Is more likely to be a psychopath: the rational moralist or the emotional amoralist?

Eating of the Tree: The phenomenology of the moral moment